Pessimism as a spur to action
Conventional economic modelling is far too sanguine about the future
Bushfire at Captain Creek, Queensland, Australia. Source: Wikimedia
The argument over whether the current price spike is transitory or something more persistent continues. For my part, both sides of the argument, as it’s usually presented, are wrong: it is a permanent shift in prices, but it’s not the result of excessive monetary financing over the last year (or indeed decade). It’s the result of the the era of cheap things coming to an end. Inflation is not “always and everywhere a monetary phenomenon”.
Either way, price rises are beginning to bite. The Financial Times picks up on one set of these, noting that its “breakfast indicator” – a composite index of the futures prices of “coffee, milk, sugar, wheat, oats and orange juice” had shot up 63% since 2019, with price rises accelerating over summer this year. The FT notes:
In a year of extreme weather, growers in key producing regions of many food commodities faced output declines. Wheat futures prices are up 20 per cent from the start of the year as Russia, North America and Argentina were affected by drought, while European producers were hit by rain. The last time wheat prices soared to current levels was in the aftermath of the 2012 drought in the US.
It has been a year of extreme weather, of course. But then so was the year before. And the year before that. Looking ahead, next year is likely to be the same. And then the year after that. And the year after that, and so on, stretching into the future. Climate change means that we should, on average, expect each year to be worse and harder than the one preceding it.
One impact of this steady decay – not the most important – is that the slight air of unreality about climate change policy is beginning to dissipate. For a period of time, it was possible for governments to make big declarations about their targets for decarbonisation, and punt these some distance into the future. This is, naturally, still happening – bonus prize this week for Australia – but those targets and, in particular, the collective failure to come even close to meeting them is beginning to feed back into conventional, short-term policymaking. The Office Budget Responsibility’s inclusion of the rising costs of climate change in its own forecasts for the path of the UK government’s debt was a positive step forward. (Then-Shadow Chancellor John McDonnell announced this would be Labour policy in autumn 2017.)
The costs of the future
These costs nonetheless remain grossly underpriced, as Nick Stern has recently noted, focusing on the use of an excessively high “discount rate” in conventional economic modelling. The discount rate is intended to capture the price of future events (typically expressed in cash flow terms) in terms of money available today. You can think about it as something like the price of the future: the higher the value of this discount rate, the more the future is “discounted” relative to the present; the lower the value, the more valuable the future will appear to be to us today. It crops up in formal cost-benefit analysis, including cost-benefit analysis of climate change policy, as a way to try and systematically present potential future costs and benefits.
In an idealised capitalist economy of “perfect capital markets” the discount rate would take the same value as the interest rate for borrowing. However, we don’t live in that idealised economy and aren’t ever going to, so the value of the discount rate has to be calculated: no capital markets exist for a whole load of future outcomes we might be interested in – it’s not possible to borrow today against the value of a marine species not being extinct in 15 years’ time, for instance.
This is where the arguments kick in. The review of the economics of climate change, led by Stern – and published, horrifyingly, 15 years ago – has a very clear walk-through of the case for believing that the discount rate we use in trying to price the future should be low – pretty close to zero. Stern’s argument is that since there are no ethical grounds for deciding that future humans are less deserving of consumption than those alive today, therefore the part of the discount rate which reflects our inherent valuation of the future (the “rate of social time preference”) must be close to zero: “the only sound ethical basis for placing less value on the utility (as opposed to consumption) of future generations was the uncertainty over whether or not the world will exist, or whether those generations will all be present.” The question of how to value the future is fundamentally an ethical one. John’s Roemer’s paper, responding to the Stern Review, has further discussion of this point.
Growth and the necessity of pessimism
I’m going to come back to the problem of extinction, since what we’re dealing with today is likely to be not the relatively near-term loss of all human life, so much as things merely becoming more and more horrible forever. For now, note that Stern doesn’t think the discount rate should simply be zero since the Review also argues that consumption growth will continue into the future as the economy grows, and that we will continue to value having more stuff to consume. This is the “Ramsey model” of discounting and, if we accept the premise that consumption growth will continue and that at the margin we always value more consumption, it makes sense (…if we further accept the methodological assumptions that a marginal utility for a “representative agent” can be aggregated to society, that individuals optimise, and that optimisation over time occurs around a given growth path: the usual neoclassical premises).
The discount rate Stern arrives at is 1.4%. To put this in context, the UK Treasury’s Green Book guidance for project appraisals by govenrment suggests that projects looking for investment should usually be evaluated with a discount rate of 3.5%. The difference between the figures amounts to the Treasury saying that (relative to opinion of the Stern Review) those born recently and those who will be born in the future have standards of living that are worth less than those born further into the past. (A flipside of this, incidentally, is that the accumulated wealth of generations past but still alive is also worth significantly more in making evaluations than the potential wealth of future generations. You can draw your own conclusions about how closely this might fit the preferences of the current government.)
But there’s another factor at work here. If we accept Stern’s argument that “there is no serious ethical argument in favour of pure-time discounting” [ie we should treat future generations’ consumption as valuable as we treat our own], we are left with a discount rate that is based (almost) entirely on the expected rate of growth, and our estimate for how valuable we think new growth will be to those alive in the future (their “marginal utility” of additional consumption).
The faster the rate of growth in the future, the higher the discount rate, since the assumption at work here is that the marginal utility of extra consumption declines as the economy grows - once we have lots of stuff already, we don’t care so much about having more, is the assumption. That means that if the rate of growth is high, we will be richer in the future than otherwise, and so any additional consumption taking place in the future will be worth less to us than consumption taking place today, when we are poorer. We are assuming (in other words) that we will all be richer in the future, anyway, so in terms of today’s consumption, we don’t care so much about consumption that takes place in the future. (Again, the reverse applies: faster future growth also means the results of past growth appears to be worth more.)
But this has the fairly direct consequence that if the expected rate of growth falls, the discount rate also falls (since people in the future will be less well off than we were expecting them to be). Shocks that produce permanent losses in growth increase the value of taking action today, since future consumption will become worth more by comparison to today – there will be less of it than we expected, so we value it more by comparison, and losses to that consumption in the future from, eg, catastrophic climate change, will appear more serious to us today.
We are, of course, still living through exactly such a negative growth shock, in the form of covid-19: even if we accept the Office for Budget Responsibility’s seriously over-optimistic calculations of those permanent impacts, growth in the future will still be reduced as a result. Throw in the rising costs of extreme weather, food shortages, future disease outbreaks and so on and, over time, the discounting model tells you that the costs of inaction now rise as growth falls away. So far, so sensible.
But note the flipside of this: excessive optimism about future growth reduces the case for taking action right now. If our conventional economic modelling is still trying to act as if 2% growth was the inevitable trend over the long term, as the OBR do (“We expect growth in output per hour to rise steadily towards 2 per cent over the long term…”), we will consistently underprice the future and underdeliver on necessary action on the climate.
It’s not just that optimism about the future is likely to be proved wrong. It’s that it is actively damaging today. Only pessimism will save us.
Owen Jones interviews John McDonnell on his podcast, reflecting on last week’s austerity-ending Budget. John attributes the switch in Conservative policy to covid-19, with the value of public services becoming apparent to everyone over the last 18 months of pandemic misery. I’m not convinced by this, since the Tories under Johnson were already pushing up spending ahead of covid. It had been clear for some time they weren’t going to return to Osborne-style spending cuts. But John’s right to flag the dire straits Starmer’s leadership is now in – and right to highlight the growing movement for change outside Parliamentary politics.
Meanwhile, Eric Gade’s recent talk on “Authorship environments” has been uploaded. Eric goes through the development of writing and literacy, and applies the same model to thinking
about how we might break computers out of their “scribal” mode (in which ony a tiny elite of the adept can claim to know how the technology works) to a version of mass literacy. Madeleine Lane-McKinley reviews Amelia Horgan’s Lost in Work in a long-form essay for the Boston Review. From a few weeks’ back, Politics Theory Other interview philosopher Amia Srivansan about her recent book, The Right to Sex. And Tribune carries a piece on the “contested politics” of Frank Herbert’s Dune, focusing on the books ahead of the film.